2016년 11월 3일 목요일

Principia Ethica 2

Principia Ethica 2


TABLE OF CONTENTS.
 
 
CHAPTER I.
 
THE SUBJECT-MATTER OF ETHICS.
 
A.
 
SECTION. PAGE
 
=1.= In order to define Ethics, we must discover what is both
common and peculiar to all undoubted ethical judgments; 1
 
=2.= but this is not that they are concerned with human
conduct, but that they are concerned with a certain predicate
‘good,’ and its converse ‘bad,’ which may be applied both to
conduct and to other things. 1
 
=3.= The subjects of the judgments of a scientific Ethics are
not, like those of some studies, ‘particular things’; 3
 
=4.= but it includes all _universal_ judgments which assert
the relation of ‘goodness’ to any subject, and hence includes
Casuistry. 3
 
B.
 
=5.= It must, however, enquire not only what things are
universally related to goodness, but also, what this predicate,
to which they are related, is: 5
 
=6.= and the answer to this question is that it is indefinable 6
 
=7.= or simple: for if by definition be meant the analysis of
an object of thought, only complex objects can be defined; 7
 
=8.= and of the three senses in which ‘definition’ can be used,
this is the most important. 8
 
=9.= What is thus indefinable is not ‘the good,’ or the whole
of that which always possesses the predicate ‘good,’ but this
predicate itself. 8
 
=10.= ‘Good,’ then, denotes one unique simple object of thought
among innumerable others; but this object has very commonly
been identified with some other--a fallacy which may be called
‘the naturalistic fallacy’ 9
 
=11.= and which reduces what is used as a fundamental principle
of Ethics either to a tautology or to a statement about the
meaning of a word. 10
 
=12.= The nature of this fallacy is easily recognised; 12
 
=13.= and if it were avoided, it would be plain that the only
alternatives to the admission that ‘good’ is indefinable, are
either that it is complex or that there is no notion at all
peculiar to Ethics--alternatives which can only be refuted by
an appeal to inspection, but which can be so refuted. 15
 
=14.= The ‘naturalistic fallacy’ illustrated by Bentham; and
the importance of avoiding it pointed out. 17
 
C.
 
=15.= The relations which ethical judgments assert to hold
universally between ‘goodness’ and other things are of two
kinds: a thing may be asserted either to _be_ good itself or to
be causally related to something else which is itself good--to
be ‘good as a means.’ 21
 
=16.= Our investigations of the latter kind of relation cannot
hope to establish more than that a certain kind of action will
_generally_ be followed by the best possible results; 22
 
=17.= but a relation of the former kind, if true at all,
will be true of all cases. All ordinary ethical judgments
assert _causal_ relations, but they are commonly treated as
if they did not, because the two kinds of relation are not
distinguished. 23
 
D.
 
=18.= The investigation of intrinsic values is complicated by
the fact that the value of a whole may be different from the
sum of the values of its parts, 27
 
=19.= in which case the part has to the whole a relation, which
exhibits an equally important difference from and resemblance
to that of means to end. 29
 
=20.= The term ‘organic whole’ might well be used to denote
that a whole has this property, since, of the two other
properties which it is commonly used to imply, 30
 
=21.= one that of reciprocal causal dependence between parts,
has no necessary relation to this one, 31
 
=22.= and the other, upon which most stress has been laid, can
be true of no whole whatsoever, being a self-contradictory
conception due to confusion. 33
 
=23.= Summary of chapter. 36
 
 
CHAPTER II.
 
NATURALISTIC ETHICS.
 
=24.= This and the two following chapters will consider certain
proposed answers to the second of ethical questions: What is
_good in itself_? These proposed answers are characterised by
the facts (1) that they declare some _one_ kind of thing to be
alone good in itself; and (2) that they do so, because they
suppose this _one_ thing to define the meaning of ‘good.’ 37
 
=25.= Such theories may be divided into two groups (1)
Metaphysical, (2) Naturalistic: and the second group may be
subdivided into two others, (_a_) theories which declare some
natural object, other than pleasure, to be sole good, (_b_)
Hedonism. The present chapter will deal with (_a_). 38
 
=26.= Definition of what is meant by ‘Naturalism.’ 39
 
=27.= The common argument that things are good, because they
are ‘natural,’ may involve either (1) the false proposition
that the ‘normal,’ as such, is good; 41
 
=28.= or (2) the false proposition that the ‘necessary,’ as
such, is good. 44
 
=29.= But a _systematised_ appeal to Nature is now most
prevalent in connection with the term ‘Evolution.’ An
examination of Mr Herbert Spencer’s Ethics will illustrate this
form of Naturalism. 45
 
=30.= Darwin’s scientific theory of ‘natural selection,’ which
has mainly caused the modern vogue of the term ‘Evolution,’
must be carefully distinguished from certain ideas which are
commonly associated with the latter term. 47
 
=31.= Mr Spencer’s connection of Evolution with Ethics seems to
shew the influence of the naturalistic fallacy; 48
 
=32.= but Mr Spencer is vague as to the ethical relations of
‘pleasure’ and ‘evolution,’ and his Naturalism may be mainly
Naturalistic Hedonism. 49
 
=33.= A discussion of the third chapter of the _Data of Ethics_
serves to illustrate these two points and to shew that Mr
Spencer is in utter confusion with regard to the fundamental
principles of Ethics. 51
 
=34.= Three possible views as to the relation of Evolution to
Ethics are distinguished from the naturalistic view to which
it is proposed to confine the name ‘Evolutionistic Ethics.’ On
any of these three views the relation would be unimportant, and
the ‘Evolutionistic’ view, which makes it important, involves a
double fallacy. 54
 
=35.= Summary of chapter. 58
 
 
CHAPTER III.
 
HEDONISM.
 
=36.= The prevalence of Hedonism is mainly due to the
naturalistic fallacy. 59
 
=37.= Hedonism may be defined as the doctrine that ‘Pleasure is
the sole good’: this doctrine has always been held by Hedonists
and used by them as a fundamental ethical principle, although
it has commonly been confused with others. 6 

댓글 없음: