2016년 11월 3일 목요일

Principia Ethica 5

Principia Ethica 5



CHAPTER VI.
 
THE IDEAL.
 
=110.= By an ‘ideal’ state of things may be meant either (1)
the Summum Bonum or absolutely best, or (2) the best which the
laws of nature allow to exist in this world, or (3) anything
greatly good in itself: this chapter will be principally
occupied with what is ideal in sense (3)--with answering the
fundamental question of Ethics; 183
 
=111.= but a correct answer to this question is an essential
step towards a correct view as to what is ‘ideal’ in senses (1)
and (2). 184
 
=112.= In order to obtain a correct answer to the question
‘What is good in itself?’ we must consider what value things
would have if they existed absolutely by themselves; 187
 
=113.= and, if we use this method, it is obvious that personal
affection and aesthetic enjoyments include by far the greatest
goods with which we are acquainted. 188
 
=114.= If we begin by considering I. _Aesthetic Enjoyments_, it
is plain (1) that there is always _essential_ to these some one
of a great variety of different emotions, though these emotions
may have little value _by themselves_: 189
 
=115.= and (2) that a cognition of really beautiful qualities
is equally essential, and has equally little value by itself. 190
 
=116.= But (3) granted that the appropriate combination of
these two elements is always a considerable good and may be
a very great one, we may ask whether, where there is _added_
to this _a true belief in the existence of the object of the
cognition_, the whole thus formed is not much more valuable
still. 192
 
=117.= I think that this question should be answered in the
affirmative; but in order to ensure that this judgment is
correct, we must carefully distinguish it 194
 
=118.= from the two judgments (_a_) that knowledge is valuable
_as a means_, (_b_) that, where the object of the cognition
is itself a good thing, its existence, of course, adds to the
value of the whole state of things: 195
 
=119.= if, however, we attempt to avoid being biassed by these
two facts, it still seems that mere true belief may be a
condition essential to great value. 197
 
=120.= We thus get a _third_ essential constituent of many
great goods; and in this way we are able to justify (1) the
attribution of value to _knowledge_, over and above its value
as a means, and (2) the intrinsic superiority of the proper
appreciation of a _real_ object over the appreciation of an
equally valuable object of mere imagination: emotions directed
towards real objects may thus, even if the object be inferior,
claim equality with the highest imaginative pleasures. 198
 
=121.= Finally (4) with regard to the _objects_ of the
cognition which is essential to these good wholes, it is the
business of Aesthetics to analyse their nature: it need only be
here remarked (1) that, by calling them ‘beautiful,’ we mean
that they have this relation to a _good_ whole; and (2) that
they are, for the most part, themselves complex wholes, such
that the admiring contemplation of the whole greatly exceeds
in value the sum of the values of the admiring contemplation of
the parts. 200
 
=122.= With regard to II. _Personal Affection_, the object is
here not merely beautiful but also good in itself; it appears,
however, that the appreciation of what is thus good in itself,
viz. the mental qualities of a person, is certainly, by itself,
not so great a good as the whole formed by the combination
with it of an appreciation of corporeal beauty; it is doubtful
whether it is even so great a good as the mere appreciation of
corporeal beauty; but it is certain that the combination of
both is a far greater good than either singly. 203
 
=123.= It follows from what has been said that we have every
reason to suppose that a cognition of _material qualities_, and
even their existence, is an essential constituent of the Ideal
or Summum Bonum: there is only a bare possibility that they are
not included in it. 205
 
=124.= It remains to consider _positive evils_ and _mixed
goods_. I. _Evils_ may be divided into three classes, namely 207
 
=125.= (1) evils which consist in the love, or admiration, or
enjoyment of what is evil or ugly 208
 
=126.= (2) evils which consist in the hatred or contempt of
what is good or beautiful 211
 
=127.= and (3) the consciousness of intense pain: this appears
to be the only thing, either greatly good or greatly evil,
which does not involve _both_ a cognition _and_ an emotion
directed towards its object; and hence it is not analogous to
pleasure in respect of its intrinsic value, while it also seems
not to add to the vileness of a whole, _as a whole_, in which
it is combined with another bad thing, whereas pleasure does
add to the goodness of a whole, in which it is combined with
another good thing; 212
 
=128.= but pleasure and pain are completely analogous in this,
that pleasure by no means always increases, and pain by no
means always decreases, the total value of a whole in which it
is included: the converse is often true. 213
 
=129.= In order to consider II. _Mixed Goods_, we must first
distinguish between (1) the value of a whole _as a whole_,
and (2) its value _on the whole_ or total value: (1) = the
difference between (2) and the sum of the values of the parts.
In view of this distinction, it then appears: 214
 
=130.= (1) That the mere combination of two or more evils is
never positively good _on the whole_, although it may certainly
have great intrinsic value _as a whole_; 216
 
=131.= but (2) That a whole which includes a cognition of
something evil or ugly may yet be a great positive good _on the
whole_: most virtues, which have any intrinsic value whatever,
seem to be of this kind, _e.g._ (_a_) courage and compassion,
and (_b_) moral goodness; all these are instances of the hatred
or contempt of what is evil or ugly; 216
 
=132.= but there seems no reason to think that, where the evil
object _exists_, the total state of things is ever positively
good _on the whole_, although the existence of the evil may add
to its value _as a whole_. 219
 
=133.= Hence (1) no actually existing evil is necessary to the
Ideal, (2) the contemplation of imaginary evils is necessary to
it, and (3) where evils already exist, the existence of mixed
virtues has a value independent both of its consequences and of
the value which it has in common with the proper appreciation
of imaginary evils. 220
 
=134.= Concluding remarks. 222
 
=135.= Summary of chapter. 224
 
 
 
 
CHAPTER I.
 
THE SUBJECT-MATTER OF ETHICS.
 
 
=1.= It is very easy to point out some among our every-day judgments,
with the truth of which Ethics is undoubtedly concerned. Whenever
we say, ‘So and so is a good man,’ or ‘That fellow is a villain’;
whenever we ask, ‘What ought I to do?’ or ‘Is it wrong for me to do
like this?’; whenever we hazard such remarks as ‘Temperance is a virtue
and drunkenness a vice’--it is undoubtedly the business of Ethics
to discuss such questions and such statements; to argue what is the
true answer when we ask what it is right to do, and to give reasons
for thinking that our statements about the character of persons or
the morality of actions are true or false. In the vast majority of
cases, where we make statements involving any of the terms ‘virtue,’
‘vice,’ ‘duty,’ ‘right,’ ‘ought,’ ‘good,’ ‘bad,’ we are making
ethical judgments; and if we wish to discuss their truth, we shall be
discussing a point of Ethics.
 
So much as this is not disputed; but it falls very far short of
defining the province of Ethics. That province may indeed be defined as
the whole truth about that which is at the same time common to all such
judgments and peculiar to them. But we have still to ask the question:

댓글 없음: